In the mathematical field of set theory, an ideal is a collection of sets that are considered to be "small" or "negligible". Every subset of an element of the ideal must also be in the ideal (this codifies the idea that an ideal is a notion of smallness), and the union of any two elements of the ideal must also be in the ideal.
More formally, given a set X, an ideal on X is a nonempty subset I of the powerset of X, such that:
Some authors add a third condition that X itself is not in I; ideals with this extra property are called proper ideals.
Ideals in the set-theoretic sense are exactly ideals in the order-theoretic sense, where the relevant order is set inclusion. Also, they are exactly ideals in the ring-theoretic sense on the Boolean ring formed by the powerset of the underlying set.
Contents |
An element of an ideal I is said to be I-null or I-negligible, or simply null or negligible if the ideal I is understood from context. If I is an ideal on X, then a subset of X is said to be I-positive (or just positive) if it is not an element of I. The collection of all I-positive subsets of X is denoted I+.
Given ideals I and J on underlying sets X and Y respectively, one forms the product I×J on the Cartesian product X×Y, as follows: For any subset A ⊆ X×Y,
That is, a set is negligible in the product ideal if only a negligible collection of x-coordinates correspond to a non-negligible slice of A in the y-direction. (Perhaps clearer: A set is positive in the product ideal if positively many x-coordinates correspond to positive slices.)
An ideal I on a set X induces an equivalence relation on P(X), the powerset of X, considering A and B to be equivalent (for A, B subsets of X) if and only if the symmetric difference of A and B is an element of I. The quotient of P(X) by this equivalence relation is a Boolean algebra, denoted P(X) / I (read "P of X mod I").
To every ideal there is a corresponding filter, called its dual filter. If I is an ideal on X, then the dual filter of I is the collection of all sets X \ A, where A is an element of I. (Here X \ A denotes the relative complement of A in X; that is, the collection of all elements of X that are not in A.)
If I and J are ideals on X and Y respectively, I and J are Rudin–Keisler isomorphic if they are the same ideal except for renaming of the elements of their underlying sets (ignoring negligible sets). More formally, the requirement is that there be sets A and B, elements of I and J respectively, and a bijection φ : X \ A → Y \ B, such that for any subset C of X, C is in I if and only if the image of C under φ is in J.
If I and J are Rudin–Keisler isomorphic, then P(X) / I and P(Y) / J are isomorphic as Boolean algebras. Isomorphisms of quotient Boolean algebras induced by Rudin–Keisler isomorphisms of ideals are called trivial isomorphisms.